Parental Rights:
'Custody' is a misleading term, for
it suggests a unitary thing when,
in fact, it refers to a set of rights
and responsibilities. In this respect,
it is like 'property'. 11 [A. M. Honore,
"Ownership] Both are convenient
labels for a cluster of rights that
have traditionally been bundled together
by social practice and in our thought.
There is a great danger of committing
"false dichotomy fallacies"
when we employ such labels without
sufficient care. With respect to property,
for example, we often think that,
absent some special arrangements,
a person must either own an item in
the strong sense that we own personal
property, or the item must be one
over which the person has no property
rights. This is, of course, mistaken,
but it is an understandable mistake
given our tendency to think of owning
property as an all-or-nothing situation.
We must be wary of these conventional
categories-€” especially when our
task is to challenge the conventions
themselves. We must ask ourselves
whether the items in the set of rights
in question are inseparable, whether
the justification for each item is
the same, and so forth. For the most
part, I shall talk about parental
rights, instead of custody, to emphasize
this.
I know of no exhaustive listing of
the set of parental rights we typically
associate with having full custody
of children. The following rights,
only some of which are relevant to
our present concern, are commonly
assumed to be included in the set:
-· the right to physical possession
of the child;
-· the right to inculcate in the child
one's moral and ethical standards,
including the right to discipline
the child;
-· the right to control and manage
a minor child's earnings and property;
-· the right to have the child bear
the parent's name;
-· the right to prevent adoption of
the child without the parents' consent;
12
-· the right to make decisions concerning
the medical treatment, education,
religious training and other activities
of the minor child; and,
-· the right to information necessary
to exercise the above rights responsibly
AND LATER ON
Bruce Hafen is perhaps more explicit:
The common law has long recognized
parental rights as a key concept,
not only for the specific purposes
of domestic relations law, but as
a fundamental cultural assumption
about the family as a basic social,
economic, and political unit. For
this reason, both English and American
judges view the origins of parental
rights as being even more fundamental
than property rights. Parental rights
to custody and control of minor children
have been variously described as 'sacred'
as a matter of 'natural law', and
as 'inherent, natural right[ s], for
the protection of which, just as much
as for the protection of the rights
of the individual to life, liberty,
and the pursuit of happiness, our
government is formed. ' These judicial
word choices imply that the parent-child
relationship antedates the state in
much the same sense as natural individual
rights are thought to antedate the
state in American political philosophy."
AND LATER:
The argument against this practice
is remarkably simple. Parental rights
are fundamental, constitutionally
guaranteed rights. 36 The procedures
for the determination of temporary
custody in divorce proceedings typically
result in the direct and substantial
deprivation of such rights without
any demonstration of the existence
of a state interest in such deprivation.
As I shall indicate shortly, the deprivation
of rights in question imposes an undue
burden on those whose rights are infringed.
These procedures, then, deprive citizens
of fundamental rights without due
process of law. They are, therefore,
unconstitutional deprivations of basic
human rights.
|